Is an originalist approach to constitutional interpretation legitimate?

Is an originalist approach to constitutional interpretation legitimate?
ISBN-10
3656348081
ISBN-13
9783656348085
Category
Political Science
Pages
7
Language
English
Published
2013-01-09
Publisher
GRIN Verlag
Author
Roy Whymark

Description

Seminar paper from the year 2012 in the subject Politics - International Politics - Region: USA, grade: 77%, Birkbeck, University of London, course: American Politics, language: English, abstract: Under Article III, Section 2 of the United States Constitution, the US Supreme Court is designated as the final court of appeal for all cases arising under the Laws, Treaties, and Constitution of the United States (U.S. Const. art. III, § 2). Although the Supreme Court’s role in determining the constitutional legitimacy of those cases brought before it is not explicitly defined, this (largely unchallenged) authority became clear during the foremost years of the republic. In his opinion on Marbury v. Madison (1803), Chief Justice Marshall noted that it was ‘emphatically the province and duty of the Judicial Department to say what the law is.’ Constitutional interpretation addresses ‘how the meaning of the constitution should be discerned, thus allowing the application of substantive constitutional law to a particular set of facts or issues’ (Thomas, 2011:1). Given the ambiguity of its language and the fact that the Constitution is a legal document written, for the most part, in 1787 under very different circumstances from today, this is a challenging undertaking and not without controversy. Indeed, the task of constitutional interpretation, and the different approaches taken by individual judges, is a major area of debate among the judiciary, the populace, and within the political and academic arenas. The position judges adopt vis-à-vis constitutional interpretation lies at the centre of court rulings concerning constitutional law. Since individual judges will have different opinions, constitutional interpretation is unavoidably dependent on the subjective views of the judges involved, whether they be legalistic, attitudinal, or other views along Posner’s spectrum of theoretical influences on judicial behaviour (Posner, 2008). This difference in approaches has been the driver of the politicisation of the judiciary and partly explains the often fractious nature of judicial confirmations. While there is no consensus regarding a singular taxonomy for constitutional interpretation, most scholars agree on the differentiation between the Originalist approach (sometimes referred to, supportively, as the Interpretivist approach) favoured by Supreme Court Justice Antonin Scalia, and other non-Originalist approaches (often referred to as non-Interpretivist approaches by their detractors). This essay considers whether the Originalist approach is the only legitimate and appropriate method of constitutional interpretation in the United States today.

Similar books

  • The Living Constitution
    By David A. Strauss

    Strauss explores how judicial decisions adapted the Constitution's text (and contradicted original intent) to produce some of our most profound accomplishments: the end of racial segregation, the expansion of women's rights, and the freedom ...

  • Living Originalism
    By Jack M. Balkin

    So argues Jack Balkin, one of the leading constitutional scholars of our time, in this long-awaited book.

  • Constitutional Originalism: A Debate
    By Robert W. Bennett, Lawrence B. Solum

    Robert H. Bork, “Neutral Principles and Some First Amendment Problems,” Indiana Law Journal 47 (1971): 13. 200. Bork, The Tempting of America, 82. 201. See generally Bennett, “'Mere' Rationality.” 202. Bork, “Neutral Principles,” 76, ...

  • Overcoming Law
    By Richard A. Posner

    Throughout, the book is unified by Posner's distinctive stance, which is pragmatist in philosophy, economic in methodology, and liberal (in the sense of John Stuart Mill's liberalism) in politics.

  • The Tempting of America
    By Robert H. Bork

    57, §§ 171, et seq.; L . 1935, pp. 94 et seq., quoted in Skinner v. Oklahoma 316 U.S. 535, ... Shapiro v. Thompson, 394 U.S. 618 (1969). 8. Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436, 479 (1966). 9. Mapp v. Ohio, 367 U.S. 643 (1961).

  • Interpreting the Constitution
    By Erwin Chemerinsky

    Interpreting The Constitution doesn't fit neatly into the extensive literature on judicial review and constitutional interpretation that reconciles judicial review with democracy defined as majority rule.

  • Originalism as Faith
    By Eric J. Segall

    Few constitutional scholars or judges argue that original meaning is irrelevant to constitutional interpretation.32 In the words of Professor Mitch Berman, “not a single self-identifying non-originalist of whom I'm aware argues that ...

  • Rethinking Constitutional Law: Originalism, Interventionism, and the Politics of Judicial Review
    By Earl M. Maltz

    Constitutional theory, Earl Maltz argues, has reached a critical impasse marked by a largely unproductive stalemate between originalists and nonoriginalists regarding the proper role of judicial review. It's time, he...

  • Original Sin: Clarence Thomas and the Failure of the Constitutional Conservatives
    By Samuel A. Marcosson

    Original Sin argues that the "jurisprudence of original intent," represented on the current Supreme Court by Justices Antonin Scalia and Clarence Thomas, has failed on its own terms.

  • Constitutional Interpretation: The Basic Questions
    By James E. Fleming, Sotirios A. Barber

    For the idea of public reason (or public reasonableness), see John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993): 212–54; John Rawls, “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited,” in John Rawls, Collected Papers ...